a blog about philosophy in public affairs

Trump vs Twitter: who has the right to do what?


“Twitter is completely stifling free speech, and I, as President, won’t allow it to happen!” Donald Trump, 27 May 2020 – published on Twitter (of course).

 

Introduction

Who has the right, to do what, on Twitter? Donald Trump’s falling out with Twitter, after Twitter’s censuring of certain tweets, has inspired accusations of bias and misbehaviour on all sides, none of which is likely to convince anyone not already convinced. But if we step outside the specific debate around Twitter’s current and future legal immunity, perhaps we can find at least one principle that might gain broad agreement: that no person has the right to do that which would prevent another person from being a person at all. And this suggests that Twitter has every right to censure Trump – and that Trump may have little right to act to censure Twitter in return.

Section 230 and unlikely allies

Section 230 of the US Communications Decency Act provides third-party hosting platforms such as Twitter and Facebook with broad legal immunity for content posted on their site, provided that they are not involved in developing that content or publishing material that violates specific laws. Section 230 also provides legal immunity for choices Twitter and others make as ‘Good Samaritans’ to restrict access to ‘objectionable’ material.

Several on the Left (loosely construed) have campaigned for Twitter to do more to prevent hateful, harassing, and false information from remaining on their site. Some have gone further, arguing that section 230 ought to be entirely revoked so that sites such as Twitter can no longer claim immunity for not acting to remove harmful content.

But it is the Right and Donald Trump who are currently amongst the most prominent in arguing that platforms such as Twitter, ought to have their right to legal immunity removed or restricted. And this is precisely because Twitter are now doing more to fact-check, place warning labels on and even remove problematic content published by Donald Trump and other world leaders.

Leaving the oddness of these bedfellows aside, who is aiming for the right outcome in section 230 repeal? Should the law be doing more to force companies like Twitter to moderate user content, or should it be doing more to force them to stop intervening in content?

The answer is neither – at least, not directly. The law should protect personhood rights, for corporate and individual persons alike. And what that means in terms of specific action will not be a blanket answer in either direction.

Corporate Personhood

The idea that corporations are persons in law is widespread. The UK holds to a ‘directing-mind’ principle in which corporate personhood is reducible to that of senior individuals. The Netherlands treat corporations as full legal persons prosecutable for any crime that a human person might be. And in the US, corporate persons are treated as having equal rights with all other persons, as a constitutional right.

It would be easy to argue that corporations are not real persons. Established by and for human persons, corporate bodies exist purely to benefit at least some collection of human persons – the board, the shareholders, the customers, the beneficiaries of the charity etc. Global giants like Twitter may have been created for those who profit from them financially, but they are successful precisely because a wider audience finds value in the service they provide.

Granting them a personhood status in the legal or moral sphere and then additionally granting them rights against human persons might seem simply perverse.

But to provide benefits to human persons, we need corporations to bear duties. We have seen what goes wrong when we fail to have a position in law which allows us to find a responsible corporate party when no individual human party can be found responsible, or has the power to provide recompense. It is therefore, at the very least, in human persons’ best interests to treat corporate persons as if they were persons in law and the social sphere, fit to bear duties, as List and Pettit suggest.

Personhood as a source of rights

And if corporations are persons with duties, it is natural to believe that they have rights. Further, those rights ought not to be denied on an ad hoc basis, depending on what human persons want at a given time. The fact that we create persons does not ordinarily allow us to determine the scope of their rights. For nightmares about the impact of doing this, watch the ‘White Christmas’ episode of Black Mirror, or read my analysis of the treatment of an artificial person in it.

But more importantly: it is dangerous for human persons, to allow ‘us’ to decide on the extent of corporate person rights on an ad hoc basis. Brexit, the rise of populism in Europe and the US, and just the long history of democratic partisan voting in most states shows that human persons do not all agree on what ‘we’ should do at all.

Many might be happy to call for restrictions on the rights of corporate persons when we believe we are on the side of ‘good’ and they are on the side of ‘bad’ – homophobic bakers, businesses trying to rip off their workforce, Social media platforms allowing harmful speech – but what happens when we disagree over who is good and who is bad?

We are finding out right now in the unofficial case of Twitter vs Donald Trump. And not everyone is happy to allow the human person Trump to decide what rights the corporate person Twitter ought to have.

A source of rights for all persons

Instead, we should be identifying what rights all persons have. Many attempts to differentiate human and corporate person rights rely on ad hoc or contested value claims.

But one thing it is hard to argue against in terms of rights is that once we have admitted any party, individual or corporate into the sphere of persons, and we expect or want them to perform as a person in the public sphere, we need to accept that they have whatever rights are needed to fulfil that role as a person in the public sphere.

Trump is so powerful that it would take the combined effort of all social and traditional media platforms, internationally, to prevent him from performing as a person in the public sphere. And maybe not even then: he’s the President of the United States. With that backdrop, it is hard to claim that his personhood is at risk in being fact-checked or censured by Twitter for publishing false information.

But a Twitter corporate person constrained by the constant fear of legal action for missing a partisan tweet, or else handcuffed against monitoring any content at all, will not be a Twitter that can perform as a person in the public sphere. Nor, perhaps, can it fulfil the duties that we ordinary persons need it to fulfil to preserve our personhood status in the public sphere – through removing hate speech that silences, allowing us to express our views alongside other persons, and protecting us from false information that would restrict us in performing our epistemic role as persons in a democracy.

Conclusion

Corporate agents are set up for us. But only by taking seriously their status as persons as a source of rights, can they effectively work for us. When it comes to Twitter vs Trump, at least for now, this means protecting the rights of Twitter.

Leonie Smith is Lecturer in Metaphysics and Epistemology at Lancaster University. Prior to this, she held a Leverhulme Early Career Fellowship at the University of Manchester, and was Lecturer in Philosophy at the University of Cardiff. Her academic work centres on the epistemic, ontological and material harms faced by people living in poverty and on the margins of society (within the UK and globally), and she runs the ‘Class in the Classroom’ workshops for academics and university staff – research-led sessions on how we can all work to help working-class students thrive at university. Alongside this, she works with the Philosophy in Prison charity, co-designing and delivering programmes and materials for UK-based prison residents.
Find out more about her work here: http://stirlingbus.com/leoniesmith/.

LinkedIn 

Previous

The harm in fake news

Next

The news media are a watchdog, but so are you

2 Comments

  1. Julia Hermann

    Thank you for this interesting post, Leonie! You are defending an original position here. I think I agree with your conclusion. I do have a question about the principle though about which you say at the beginning of the post that we might gain broad agreement about it, the principle that “no person has the right to do that which would prevent another person from being a person at all”. I wonder how strong that principle is as a basis for the position you arrive at. The broad agreement that might be gained seems to be concerned with persons in the more intuitive sense, which does not include corporations. I see the purpose of giving corporations the status of persons, in particular legal status, but I find it harder to understand what it means to prevent a person that is a corporation from being a person at all. My impression is that this principle loses plausibility once we take persons to include corporate persons. When we think about what it could mean to prevent a human person from being a person at all, we can think of severely limiting a person’s autonomy or rationality, for instance. It is unclear what it can mean to severely limit a corporation’s autonomy or rationality.

    • Thanks so much for this thoughtful question Julia, it’s a really great point. And I think it links to broader questions about what it means to say we *ought* to protect a person’s personhood status. For example, it seems absolutely fine to say that we can disband a corporation at will, effectively taking its ‘life’ or personhood status, but the same is not true of an individual (although some might think we can make exceptions for conscription into wars etc., it is still considered to be a major sacrifice). I couldn’t say a great deal more within the constraints of this short post, but this wider point is something I consider in the paper these ideas are based on a bit more (although I still think more could and needs to be said).

      Here I will just add two things. The first is that, with regard to what it would mean to limit a corporation’s autonomy or rationality, I think the way I would consider it is to ask this: ‘what rights do corporate persons actually need in order to function as those persons, in the spheres that we have created them to perform within’? Whatever rights they need to do *that*, will be the rights that their personhood status grants them protection of. It would be no more than this, and it’s no less, if we want to be avoid their arbitrary domination by powerful or corrupt individual persons and so on. So this might include the right to make decisions, and to speak freely (unless specific actions would undermine other persons’ ability to perform as persons) and so on. And this, I think, is the kind of position that does make sense for us to hold. Whatever other sources of rights we might think there are (to further autonomy or in other spheres, so maybe rights to religious freedom, to a family life), the basic ones any ‘person’ is entitled to are those that are necessary for their performance as a person according to what it takes to be a person in the spheres they are expected to perform as a person within.

      And the second, is that there’s a general point at stake here I think in which, we don’t have to grant *any* non-human entity personhood, but once we do (in order to say, require that it fulfils duties) we can’t just undermine or remove that personhood at will but rather, have to do so with due consideration for the significance of doing that. So whilst we can terminate a corporate person, for example, we ought not to do it arbitrarily or in such a way that we effectively make it impossible for *any* corporate persons to be persons, because nobody can know if we can actually rely on the continued existence of that person when it comes to entering into contracts and promises with them etc.

Leave a Reply

Your email address will not be published. Required fields are marked *

Powered by WordPress & Theme by Anders Norén