a blog about philosophy in public affairs

What are the values of the left?

This a guest post by Marius Ostrowski (Examination Fellow in Politics at All Souls College, University of Oxford). He is the author of the recently published book Left Unity: Manifesto for a Progressive Alliance.

‘Being on the left’ can mean a variety of different things. Most commonly, it refers in a partisan sense to support for ‘progressive’ policies designed to bring about political, economic, or social equality. More generally, it is seen as synonymous with radicalism of opinion, and a greater willingness to reform rather than preserve the status quo. In a religious context especially, ‘the left’ is used to describe anti-dogmatic or anti-orthodox tendencies in favour of departing from inherited customs or scriptural interpretations. Sometimes it is identified with activism or protest in defence of specific groups in society: the working class, women, people of colour, national/religious minorities, LGBTQ*, or the disabled. Not all of these meanings of ‘leftness’ are compatible with one another. But despite the differences between them, one thing emerges very clearly: ideas such as ‘leftness’ and ‘being on the left’ play a central role in many areas of social life.

Where the concept of ‘leftness’ is not typically so much at home is in social philosophy. This is not to suggest that social philosophers themselves are hostile to the left or uninterested in left causes. Many are card-carrying activists and partisans of the left movement. Rather, the concept itself—like its relatives ‘centre’ and ‘right’—is somewhat alien to social-philosophical analysis. In general, it is rare to hear social philosophy make any explicit mention of ‘ideologies’. We are far more likely to encounter ‘theories’, ‘accounts’, or ‘comprehensive doctrines’, even when applied to what are clearly ideological constructions, such as ‘political liberalism’. Key social-philosophical concepts such as democracy, authority, or rights are dealt with as if in a vacuum, removed from any ideological connotations or parsing they might have. It is as though social philosophy is embarrassed by ideology—with ‘leftness’ only one of several victims of this embarrassment.

Given the sheer social importance of ‘leftness’ and similar ideological notions, it is worth subjecting the concept to closer scrutiny. In general terms, ‘the left’ appeals to two core propositions, the first an interpretative claim about the world, the second an action-guiding principle that leads on from it:

  1. Interpretative claim: A view of the world as divided into ‘those with’ and ‘those without’, advantaged and disadvantaged, privileged and underprivileged (in terms of resources, status, options/opportunities, abilities/capacities, or anything else that can belong or be ascribed differently to human beings);
  2. Action-guiding principle: A resolution to fight for ‘those without’ and against ‘those with’, particularly in so far as ‘those with’ cause or perpetuate the ‘without-ness’ of ‘those without’.

These propositions ground several left concerns, each of which the left conceives in terms of a positive/negative dichotomy. One is with the distribution and uses of social power, where the left advocates for the widest possible empowerment and resists instances of oppression. Another is with the deep structure of society, for which the left seeks to foster parity within and between social groups, and dissolve hierarchy in their arrangement towards each other. A third is with social attitudes, where the left fights to extend recognition among people and their respective views, and opposes discrimination between them. Lastly, the left is concerned with behaviour, embracing friendly cooperation between people in pursuit of shared projects of human flourishing, and rejecting hostile competition to achieve gains at others’ expense.

***

Who is it that subscribes to these propositions and concerns? Or, very simply put, who counts as belonging to the left? On the face of it, some possible answers to this question come to mind fairly readily. Most countries’ political systems contain more-or-less popular parties that identify as ‘left-wing’—communist, socialist, social-democratic, liberal, green. Their economies or civil societies may feature trade unions, cooperative businesses, pressure-groups, or charities that share left priorities. But it is not enough to automatically equate ‘leftness’ with the social presence of any of these bodies (or even all of them, however inclusively defined). For a start, very few of them ever impose ‘leftness’ as an ideological criterion on their would-be membership. All of these bodies can accommodate personnel (even entire ‘wings’) that veer towards the ‘centre’ or the ‘right’. Further, they are liable to ideological migration over time. As power shifts, structures transform, and attitudes and behaviour evolve, their particular sectional concerns may drift—in extremis, from fighting for ‘those without’ to defending ‘those with’.

Although ‘left’ is usually described as something we ‘are’, identity is a fairly poor criterion for ‘leftness’. This is true even of as fundamental an identity as the division between ‘those with’ and ‘those without’. Not all ‘those without’ side with the left: some are concerned only with fighting for themselves, and are prepared to help ‘those with’ prolong or worsen ‘without-ness’, at least for others in their position. In turn, not all ‘those with’ side against the left: some are more than willing to join the fight on behalf of ‘those without’, and to impose limits on ‘with-ness’, both for themselves and others like them. Being on the left is less a matter of personal attributes or membership of certain groups than what form our social fight takes—less about who we are than about what we do.

‘Leftness’ as a form of action is associated with certain values—both in their pursuit as characteristics of a social end-state and their practice as the means of getting there. Broadly defined, they are:

  • (1) Freedom: Emancipating people from being held under forceful control, and giving them opportunities to exercise conscious choice over their lives without arbitrary constraints or coercion.
  • (2) Equality: Bringing about situations where people are of the same or similar standing in certain important respects, or by certain criteria of measurement.
  • (3) Justice: Ensuring that people are treated and provided for fairly, adequately, and correctly, according to their rightful due.
  • (4) Solidarity: Recognising the reciprocal bonds and shared purposes that tie people together, and their duties to support each other in their mutual common interest.
  • (5) Pluralism: Acknowledging that people are separate individuals who belong to various groups, and encouraging people to foster the many heterogeneous and incommensurable aspects of their identities.
  • (6) Progress: Pursuing the continuous onward advance of society by developing ever new and better ways to bring about improvements in people’s lives.

Certainly, each of these can mean different things to different people on the left. Freedom can be read as individual, group, or geographical autonomy from state authority, or as the collective removal of entire classes from the yoke of economic exploitation. Justice can take the form of welfarist redistribution, social insurance schemes, public service provision, or even tolerance for cultural diversity. Progress is sometimes conceived as the development of society’s overall cultural or technological capabilities, and at other times by the achievement of individual flourishing and enlightenment.

Likewise, these values can be more-or-less central to left ideologies. Equality is often an incidental by-product of other priorities, such as the end of rapacious resource extraction, the end of militaristic imperialism, or the collective appropriation of the means of production. Solidarity on the basis of class, gender, ethnic groups, etc., is key to trade unionism, feminism, and race politics conceived in a socialist mould, but is often downplayed in favour of expanding individual rights by movements inflected with liberal commitments. Finally, pluralism is sometimes pushed into a subordinate position relative to different ideologies’ ‘red line’ commitments, whether the primacy of economic class, the urgency of addressing climate catastrophe, or the inexcusability of state coercion.

There is a limit to how far we can pin down the absolute definitions and relative rankings of these values, even though much of the debate within the left is directly or indirectly about this question. Of course, contextual differences in time and place play a key role in disrupting any such efforts at ‘clarification’—as, for instance, with the historical evolution of ‘classical liberalism’ via ‘social liberalism’ through into today’s rival ‘high liberalism’ and ‘neoliberalism’, or the nuanced differences between national traditions of Cold War-era communism despite their shared Marxian origins. Yet more generally, imposing any firm or exclusive determination of definitions or rankings ascribes to the left a monolithic nature that it does not possess. Certainly, appeals to these six values figure extensively in left thinking. But while the labels stay the same, their contents quiver and twist incessantly, and their frequency and setting fluctuates dramatically between (and within) left thinkers’ usages. Any attempt to keep the concept of ‘leftness’ broad and inclusive—and above all focused on the action of individual people—avoids pushing this set of values past the point of overarching ‘family resemblance’. Having already discounted essential fixity of identity as a qualifying criterion for ‘leftness’, we cannot now replace it with an essential fixity of values.

***

What is the function of these values? To appreciate this, we have to draw a distinction in social thinking between diagnosis and critique. There is nothing necessarily ‘left’ about diagnosing the existence and nature of social power, structures, attitudes, and behaviour. What is ‘left’ is framing them in terms of specific dichotomies, and giving the opposing parts of these dichotomies positive and negative valences. Empowerment/oppression, recognition/discrimination, etc., are not manifest in society as such. What is manifest are certain distributions and uses of power, certain substantive and targeted attitudes, etc., but their oppressive and discriminatory character first have to be read into them. This reading—and especially which way round the positive/negative associations of the two sides of each dichotomy lie—requires us to supply certain values (with whatever justification) that we feel to be missing (for whatever reason). It is these values and the apparatuses of argumentation attached to them that enable us to look at society and say ‘but wait, hold on…’.

Critique is not universal or neutral, but intensely ideological. The nature of our critical outlook depends on which values it is that we deliberately search for—or, more commonly, whose absence we feel most keenly. By way of example, we can see this by comparing the values of the left to those embraced by the right:

  • Some of the right’s values are the direct inverse of the left’s: an acceptance or endorsement of inequality as natural, necessary, or desirable; monism about the importance of single, fixed views of good/bad, right/wrong in sustaining culture and the results of civilisation.
  • Others are new and separate, entirely unrelated to those of the left: an embrace of order and stability in the face of change viewed as inherently chaotic and destructive; the elevation of faith as a source of social truth and guide for social argument; and an adherence to tradition and custom as a way to preserve society’s integrity over time.
  • But some are rival versions of the left’s own values, and much of both the left and right’s energy is devoted to turf wars to determine which of them gets to claim these values as their own. Freedom is conceived by the right almost entirely in individual terms, and focused disproportionately towards speech and commercial entrepreneurship; justice takes the guise of legal discipline, which polices and punishes criminality; and solidarity is targeted above all at familial, religious, or national groups and identity.

These values underpin a set of rightist critiques that are incommensurable and incommunicable to those of the left. For example, the worst oppression in society is the taxation of hardworking successful businesspeople by the tyrannical majority in the name of democracy. Society does not need fewer hierarchies, but just has to put better (cleverer, more naturally gifted) people in charge. The real discrimination is against ordinary people trying to keep alive our society’s long-held Judaeo-Christian beliefs against the latest fads of solipsistic identity politics. Society could do with more competition, not less, to incentivise better outcomes in stagnant public-sector monopolies.

To the left, these claims sound either offensive or ridiculous—how could social diagnosis lead to those social critiques! But to those on the right, they are reasonable to the point of being self-evident—how could they not! Of course, we know instinctively that the world looks very different to the right than it does to the left. Yet the point is to know exactly how they differ, in order to grasp how rival value-sets and pathways of social critique are arrayed against each other in left-right ideological contests.

In sum, there is no such thing as value-free critique. What we feel in response to our diagnoses of society decides which ideological side our critique takes. In this context, freedom, equality, justice, solidarity, pluralism, and progress—not separately but in combination—are what makes social thinking left, as opposed to anything else. First and foremost, they form the left’s conceptual arsenal, orienting its reasoning and anchoring its rhetoric. More deeply, they are the lenses through which the left sees the world, the ‘standout features’ on the left’s map of society. But above all, they are the bridge that allows left thinking to move from social science to social ethics—a way for different left groups and ideologies to build a discursive moral universe around their core concern in favour of ‘those without’.

In this context, the fine-grained stipulation pursued by social philosophy of what precisely each of these values mean in isolation can only be part of the story. Social philosophers also need to look at the bigger picture: how these values relate to each other, how they join together to construct a left worldview, how they inform left critique, and how they guide left action.

Previous

Should Parties Be Democratic?

Next

What (if anything) is wrong with child labour?

1 Comment

  1. Thank you for the interesting post. The only thing on which I would slightly disagree is the association of the left with progress. Firstly, because it suggests a philosophy of history that can be contested. Secondly, because a good part of what left-wing parties currently do, in welfare states contexts, is trying to preserve the achievements of the welfare state – a conservative move, thus. Thus, if the left keeps repeating that being conservative is always bad and that reforms are always valuable, it’s easier for the right to blame socialist parties for their conservatism and reluctance to “modernize” welfare states.

Leave a Reply

Your email address will not be published. Required fields are marked *

Powered by WordPress & Theme by Anders Norén